The Ethical Consequences of Competition
If all nature is at war, with the creatures struggling for
existence with each other, and if human life is another form
of natural life, then humans must also be caught up in this
struggle for survival.
If so, then it follows that, rather than be charitable,
compassionate, or altruisitic, humans should be brutal, ruthless,
and murderous.
This has presented an problem for the advocates
of Darwinism, because such an ethical code runs entirely counter
to Christian ( and Buddhist, Islamic, Judaic ) religious teachings,
as well as moral theories developed by subsequent thinkers.
Either Darwinians had to accept the moral implications of Darwinism
for human life, or else refuse. The other option was simply to
deny the importance or the reality of Darwin's war of nature.
Acceptance
Darwin himself appears to have always accepted the murderous
implications of his idea in human life:
When two races of men meet they act precisely like two species of animals - they fight, eat each other, bring diseases to each other &c,
but then comes the more deadly struggle, namely which have the best
fitted organisation, or instincts (ie. intellect in man) to gain the
day.
(Darwin. 1839 notebooks)
At some future period, not very distant as measured by centuries, the civilised races of man will almost certainly exterminate, and replace, the savage races throughout the world. At the same time the anthropomorphous apes, as Professor Schaaffhausen has remarked, will no doubt be exterminated. The break between man and his nearest allies will then be wider, for it will intervene between man in a more civilised state, as we may hope, even than the Caucasian, and some ape as low as a baboon, instead of as now between the negro or Australian and the gorilla.
(Darwin. The Descent of Man. Chapter VI)
The more civilised so-called Caucasian races have beaten the Turks
hollow in the struggle for existence. Looking at the world at no
very distant date, what an endless number of lower races will have
been eliminated by the higher civilised races throughout the world.
(Darwin. Letter to W. Graham. 3 July 1881)
(from Darwinian Impacts. Ch.16 D.R.Oldroyd. Open University. 1980)
Sociobiologists, it appears, also accept:
The economy of nature is competitive from beginning to end.
Understand that economy, and how it works, and the underlying
reasons for social phenomena are manifest. They are the means
by which one organism gains some advantage to the detriment of
another. No hint of genuine charity ameliorates our vision of
society, once sentimentalism has been laid aside. What passes
for cooperation turns out to be a mixture of opportunism and
exploitation... Scratch an altruist, and watch a hypocrite
bleed.
(Sociobiologist M.T. Ghiselin. The Economy of Nature and the Evolution of Sex. 1974)
Adolf Hitler was probably the one person who not only accepted the
moral implications of Darwinism, but acted upon them:
Nobody can doubt that this world will one day be the scene of dreadful struggles for existence on the part of mankind. In the end the instinct of self-preservation alone will triumph. Before its consuming fire this so-called humanitarianism, which connotes only a mixture of fatuous timidity and self-conceit, will melt away as under the March sunshine. Man has become great through perpetual struggle. In perpetual peace his greatness must decline.
(Hitler. Mein Kampf. Chapter 4.)
If we do not respect the law of nature, imposing our will by the might
of the stronger, a day would come when the wild animals would again
devour us, and the insects would eat the wild animals, and finally
nothing would exist except the microbes... The law of selection
justifies this incessant struggle by allowing the survival of the
fittest. Christianity is a rebellion against natural law, a protest
against nature.
(Hitler. Table Talk.)
In Mein Kampf Hitler had written years before, 'A stronger race will drive out the weaker ones, for the vital urge in its ultimate form will break down the absurd barriers of the so-called humanity of individuals to make way for the humanity of Nature which destroys the weak to give their place to the strong.' That is the law of the jungle: little wonder that it brought in its train so much misery, agony, destruction and death.
(Russell. The Scourge of the Swastika.)
A great deal has been written to put distance between Hitler and
the Darwinian theory of evolution. Hitler, it is said, employed a
crude blending theory of evolution. But then, so did Darwin, who knew
nothing of Mendelian genetics. Hitler's eugenic ideas, his ideas of
higher and lower races, were the common currency of his age. What was
remarkable about Hitler was not what he believed, but that he acted
on those beliefs. Hitler acted upon Darwin's logic of intense
intra-specific competition, by setting out to systematically
eliminate competitors - Jews, Gypsies, Slavs. Hitler behaved as an
exemplary Darwinian competitor.
And indeed a process of "natural selection" was suggested during the Wannsee Conference of 1942 in which the transport and elimination of European Jews was discussed.
Able-bodied Jews, separated according to sex, will be taken in large work columns to these areas for work on roads, in the course of which action doubtless a large portion will be eliminated by natural causes.
The possible final remnant will, since it will undoubtedly consist of the most resistant portion, have to be treated accordingly, because it is the product of natural selection and would, if released, act as a the seed of a new Jewish revival
(Adolf Eichmann. Wannsee Conferences minutes. January 1942)
This process of "natural selection" was only to operate on able-bodied Jews. This entailed a prior "selection" and segregation of the able-bodied and un-able-bodied. The able-bodied were inducted into the labour camps to be worked to death, while the remainder were disposed of on the spot.
Refusal
A. R. Wallace, co-founder with Darwin of the theory of evolution by
natural selection, could never bring himself to consent to this brutalisation.
For him, human beings were distinguished form brute nature through
being spiritual beings, and in his later years Wallace turned
to mysticism.
Thomas Huxley - Darwin's 'bulldog' - also refused to accept that
natural selection by competitive exclusion was applicable to humans.
No one is more strongly convinced than I am of the vastness of the
gulf between civilised man and the brutes, or is more certain that
whether from them or not, he is assuredly not of them.
(T.H.Huxley from Nature's Economy. Ch. 9. Donald Worster. Cambridge 1985)
For Huxley, morality was a human invention. Nature was the model
of depravity, and "the headquarters of the enemy of ethical virtue."
In more recent times, Richard Dawkins has also set out to separate
humanity from the natural world:
We [humans] have at least the mental equipment to foster our long-term
selfish interests rather than merely our short-term selfish interests.
We can see the long-term benefits of participating in a 'conspiracy
of doves', and we can sit down together to discuss ways of making the
conspiracy work. We have the power to defy the selfish genes of our
birth and, if necessary, the selfish memes of our indoctrination.
We can even discuss ways of deliberately cultivating and nurturing
pure, disinterested altruism - something that has no place in nature,
something that has never existed before in the whole history of the
world. We are built as gene machines and cultured as meme machines,
but we have the power to turn against our creators. We, alone on
earth, can rebel against the tyranny of the selfish replicators.
(Richard Dawkins. The Selfish Gene. Ch. 11. Oxford 1989)
Brave words, but how come "we alone" can rebel against our selfish
genes? What special dispensation does human life have, which has been
denied to all previous forms of life? And for every Richard Dawkins
and Thomas Huxley who deny the continuity of human life with all
preceding natural life, surely there will be one or two men who will
accept that continuity, deny any special dispensation for human
life, and draw quite different conclusions?
Denial
Another line of argument simply downplays competition and the
struggle for existence, and replaces it with reproductive
success as the measure of fitness. Darwin's war of nature is
gently ushered offstage. The competitive imperative is replaced by
a reproductive imperative.
Whenever one organism leaves more successful offspring than another,
in time its genes will come to dominate the population gene pool.
Eventually the genotype leaving fewer offspring must become extinct
in a stable population, unless there are concomitant changes
conferring an advantage on it as it becomes rarer. Thus ultimately,
natural selection operates only by differential reproductive
success. Differential mortality can be selective but only
to the degree that it creates differences between individuals in the
number of reproductive progeny they leave.
Hence Darwin's choice of words, such as "struggle for existence"
and "survival of the fittest," have had a most unfortunate
consequence. They have tended to make people think in terms of a
dog-eat-dog world and to consider such things as predation and fighting
over food as the prevalent means of selection. All too often natural
selection is couched in terms of differential death rates, and the
strongest and fastest individuals are considered to have a selective
advantage over weaker and slower individuals. But if this were the
case, every species would continually gain in strength and speed.
(Evolutionary Ecology. 3rd Ed. Eric R. Pianka. Harper and Row 1983
Original emphases.)
Competition becomes occasional, as the reproductive imperative
takes over.
The phrase "struggle for existence" is unfortunate. It carries too
many overtones of "Nature red in tooth and claw." True, predatory
animals do play a part in reducing the number of surviving members
of a population, and hence in determining which members will
contribute most to the next generation. But competition for available
food supply is also a factor, operating principally in times of
exceptional stringency, as, for example, during droughts, floods,
exceptionally severe or prolonged winters, or as a result of extreme
overpopulation of a given territory...
"Individuals having most offspring are the fittest ones (Lerner, 1959).
It is well to remember that this is what "fittest" means in natural
selection theory, and all that it means. Much mistaken thinking to
the contrary notwithstanding, "fittest" does not mean "strongest" or
"fastest" or "healthiest" or "most intelligent."
(Paul Moody. Introduction to Evolution. 2nd Ed. Harper. 1962)
Another approach is to deny that the fact of a struggle for
existence in the natural world has any ethical consequences for
humans. The attempt to draw moral lessons from natural facts
is often called the 'naturalistic fallacy', which asserts
that it is not possible to derive a prescriptive conclusion from a
descriptive premise: one cannot derive an "ought" from an "is".
Just because there is a struggle for existence in the natural
world, it does not follow that humans ought to behave like
animals.
Since the middle of the nineteenth century, repeated attempts have
been made - and sociobiology represents the most recent one - to
ground morals on ethologico-evolutionary considerations. The ability
to adopt a moral code may indeed be viewed as an aspect of human
behaviour. It must, therefore, have been shaped by selective,
evolutionary forces in the same way as, for instance, the ability
to speak, what Noam Chomsky calls a 'deep structure'. In this
perspective, it is the task of biologists to explain how human
beings have evolved their capacity to hold ethical beliefs.
This, however, does not apply to the content of these beliefs.
It is not because something is 'natural' that it is 'right'...
In fact, the search for biological answers to questions of ethics
represents a confusion between what Kant considered to be two quite
distinct categories. It is driven by the ideology of scientism, the
belief that the methods and insights of the natural sciences will
account for all aspects of human activity. Such a belief underlies
the equivocal terminology used by many sociobiologists, as well as
some of their unwarranted suppositions and extrapolations from
animal to human behaviour.
(Francois Jacob. The Possible and the Actual. 1982)
Christian Creationism may not be so much an objection to the idea
of evolution itself, but to the ethical consequences of accepting
the Darwinian idea of evolution by competitive exclusion.
Rather than accept the all-too-obvious moral consequences of
this version of evolution, some Christians have preferred to
throw out the whole idea of evolution, lock, stock, and barrel.
Conclusion
Some 150 years on, the Darwinian struggle for existence still has
its adherents. For them, life is the war of all against all, and some
of them have fully adopted its competitive imperative. Others, while
accepting the Darwinian struggle, have exempted human life from this
struggle.
But, more recently, a reproductive imperative has begun to edge
out the competitive imperative. Once reproduction becomes the central
imperative of life, the moral problem of Darwinian competition simply
fades away.
This shift oddly coincides with a wider shift in social mentality.
The Victorians admired mastery, strength, pugnacity, toughness and
determination. Such qualities, in the late 20th Century, are not
admired so highly, if at all. Sexual liberation from Victorian prudery,
assisted by psychologists such as Freud, has given sex a new primacy
in human life. The advocates of a reproductive imperative may thus
have encountered a receptiveness to their ideas which would have been
absent a century earlier.
But perhaps more generally, those scientists who see their task as
describing the natural world, stating what is the case, regularly
deny that it is any business of theirs, as scientists, to state what
ought to be the case.